Results for 'Can We Believe What We Do'

963 found
Order:
  1. Francois Recanati.Can We Believe What We Do - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Can we believe what we do not understand?François Recanati - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):84-100.
    In a series of papers, Sperber provides the following analysis of the phenomenon of ill-understood belief (or 'quasi-belief', as I call it): (i) the quasi-believer has a validating meta-belief, to the effect that a certain representation is true; yet (ii) that representation does not give rise to a plain belief, because it is 'semi-propositional'. In this paper I discuss several aspects of this treatment. In particular, I deny that the representation accepted by the quasi-believer is semantically indeterminate, and I reject (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  3.  21
    How Can We Believe those Stories? A Nordic Perspective The Ethical Grounds of Competing Truth-claims.Frank Bylov - 2013 - Ethics and Social Welfare 7 (3):232-240.
    This paper discusses the different, often competing, even conflicting, truth-claims that are heard around the personal narratives of marginalized, stigmatized and culturally muted people?in this case people with intellectual disabilities. Since people with intellectual disabilities began speaking up in the 1980s, tensions have emerged as to whose voice is authentic, whose story can be believed. This matters because we see the consequences of failure to believe those stories in scandals of abuse in settings, such as Winterbourne View (England) in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  99
    What can we not do at will and why.Hagit Benbaji - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (7):1941-1961.
    Recently it has been argued that we cannot intend at will. Since intentions cannot be true or false, our involuntariness cannot be traced to “the characteristic of beliefs that they aim at truth”, as Bernard Williams convincingly argues. The alternative explanation is that the source of involuntariness is the shared normative nature of beliefs and intentions. Three analogies may assimilate intentions to beliefs vis-à-vis our involuntariness: first, beliefs and intentions aim at something; second, beliefs and intentions are transparent to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. What Do We Aim At When We Believe?Conor Mchugh - 2011 - Dialectica 65 (3):369-392.
    It is often said that belief aims at truth. I argue that if belief has an aim then that aim is knowledge rather than merely truth. My main argument appeals to the impossibility of forming a belief on the basis of evidence that only weakly favours a proposition. This phenomenon, I argue, is a problem for the truth-aim hypothesis. By contrast, it can be given a simple and satisfying explanation on the knowledge-aim hypothesis. Furthermore, the knowledge-aim hypothesis suggests a very (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  6.  13
    What We Can Do with Words: Essays on the Relationship Between Linguistic and Non-Linguistic Theorizing.Patrick Shirreff - 2018 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
    The essays that make up my dissertation share a methodological approach that aims to explore the philosophical implications of linguists' accounts of ordinary language use. In particular, all of them focus on epistemic natural language and the implications that linguists' accounts of such language has for epistemology. The first essay focuses on the debate about the norms that govern assertion and shows the ways in which research on natural language evidentiality has direct bearing. This essay uses existing cross-linguistic data about (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  41
    Why Can’t We Do What They Do? National Health Reform Abroad.Timothy Stoltzfus Jost - 2004 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32 (3):433-441.
    Even Americans who have only a vague knowledge of health policy know that the U.S. is different. We do not have “socialized medicine,” like our European or Canadian neighbors. We believe that health care is not rationed here, and that, unlike citizens of other nations, we do not have to wait in long queues when we need medical care. We believe that U.S. health care is the best in the world.At the same time, the U.S. spends more on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  87
    Believing what we do not believe: Acquiescence to superstitious beliefs and other powerful intuitions.Jane L. Risen - 2016 - Psychological Review 123 (2):182-207.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  9. Can We Be Self-Deceived about What We Believe? Self-Knowledge, Self-Deception, and Rational Agency.Mathieu Doucet - 2011 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (S1):E1-E25.
    Abstract: This paper considers the question of whether it is possible to be mistaken about the content of our first-order intentional states. For proponents of the rational agency model of self-knowledge, such failures might seem very difficult to explain. On this model, the authority of self-knowledge is not based on inference from evidence, but rather originates in our capacity, as rational agents, to shape our beliefs and other intentional states. To believe that one believes that p, on this view, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10.  37
    Can we believe what we know?Harold Morick - 1980 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 40 (3):406-410.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  42
    What We Can Learn From Literary Authors.Alberto Voltolini - 2021 - Acta Analytica 36 (4):479-499.
    That we can learn something from literature, as cognitivists claim, seems to be a commonplace. However, when one considers matters more deeply, it turns out to be a problematic claim. In this paper, by focusing on general revelatory facts about the world and the human spirit, I hold that the cognitivist claim can be vindicated if one takes it as follows. We do not learn such facts from literature, if by “literature” one means the truth-conditional contents that one may ascribe (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12. To what extent can we overcome the „bystander effects‟ of collective responsibility in matters of global injustice?“.Isabelle Baker - 2011 - Emergent Australasian Philosophers 4 (1).
    Where do we draw the line between individual and collective responsibilities? Can collectives be „morally responsible‟ in the same way that individuals can? This paper explores the Bystander Effect – how an individual‟s sense of personal responsibility can become „diffused‟ when they become part of a collective. This is compared to the issue of the collective responsibility of the „developed world‟ to aid the „Third World‟ that ethicists, such Peter Singer and Iris Marion Young believe to be true. I (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. What can we Know a priori?Carrie Jenkins - unknown
    Michael Devitt has been developing an influential two-pronged attack on the a priori for over thirteen years. This attack does not attempt to undermine the coherence or significance of the distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori, but rather to answer the question: 'What Can We Know A Priori?' with: 'Nothing'. In this paper I explain why I am dissatisfied with key extant responses to Devitt's attack, and then take my own steps towards resisting the attack as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  7
    A comprehensive history of Western ethics: what do we believe?Warren Ashby - 2005 - Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. Edited by W. Allen Ashby.
    "Ashby includes the great thinkers and periods that have shaped Western ethics: the Greeks, the Hebrew prophets, the Roman Stoics, St. Augustine, the medieval ethicists, the Renaissance and Reformation, the Enlightenment, the Romantics, and the radical revolutions of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. In the period from 1850 to 1920, Ashby notes, the transformations wrought by the four great modern thinkers - Darwim, Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud - both extended and significantly challenged the traditional core beliefs of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Can we do without pragmatic encroachment.Brian Weatherson - 2005 - Philosophical Perspectives 19 (1):417–443.
    I consider the problem of how to derive what an agent believes from their credence function and utility function. I argue the best solution of this problem is pragmatic, i.e. it is sensitive to the kinds of choices actually facing the agent. I further argue that this explains why our notion of justified belief appears to be pragmatic, as is argued e.g. by Fantl and McGrath. The notion of epistemic justification is not really a pragmatic notion, but it is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   203 citations  
  16. Why Do We Believe What We Are Told?Angus Ross - 1986 - Ratio (1):69-88.
    It is argued that reliance on the testimony of others cannot be viewed as reliance on a kind of evidence. Speech being essentially voluntary, the speaker cannot see his own choice of words as evidence of their truth, and so cannot honestly offer them to others as such. Rather, in taking responsibility for the truth of what he says, the speaker offers a guarantee or assurance of its truth, and in believing him the hearer accepts this assurance. I argue (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  17.  15
    The grand delusion: what we know but don't believe.Steve Hagen - 2020 - Somerville, MA, USA: Wisdom Publications.
    Robert Pirsig wrote of Steve Hagen's first book, Why the World Doesn't Seem to Make Sense, "For those who are certain that objectivity and intellect are the ground floor of all knowledge, this can be a valuable trip to the sub-basement." Now, in The Grand Delusion, Hagen drills deeper, into the most basic strengths, assumptions, and limitations of religion and belief, philosophy and inquiry, science, and technology. In doing so, he shines new light on the question Why is there Something (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  45
    What Do We Do about Bleakness?Alan Holland - 2011 - Environmental Values 20 (3):315 - 321.
    In response to Robin Attfield, I am inclined, still, (a) to claim that the concept of value cannot do the kind of comparative work that he asks it to do; (b) to doubt that the value of our world can be founded on the flourishing to be found there; and (c) to believe that there is enough in the world to be glad about even if it does not contain a preponderance of value. In response to John Cottingham, (a) (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  30
    Do Retinal Neurons Also Represent Somatosensory Inputs? On Why Neuronal Responses Are Not Sufficient to Determine What Neurons Do.Lotem Elber-Dorozko & Yonatan Loewenstein - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (4):e13265.
    How does neuronal activity give rise to cognitive capacities? To address this question, neuroscientists hypothesize about what neurons “represent,” “encode,” or “compute,” and test these hypotheses empirically. This process is similar to the assessment of hypotheses in other fields of science and as such is subject to the same limitations and difficulties that have been discussed at length by philosophers of science. In this paper, we highlight an additional difficulty in the process of empirical assessment of hypotheses that is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  21
    What Can We Believe.Peter A. Bertocci - 1950 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (4):597-598.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Epistemic Paradise Lost: Saving What We Can with Stable Support.Anna-Maria A. Eder - 2021 - In Nick Hughes (ed.), Epistemic Dilemmas. Oxford University Press.
    I focus on the No-Paradise Dilemma, which results from some initially plausible epistemic ideals, coupled with an assumption concerning our evidence. Our evidence indicates that we are not in an epistemic paradise, in which we do not experience cognitive failures. I opt for a resolution of the dilemma that is based on an evidentialist position that can be motivated independently of the dilemma. According to this position, it is rational for an agent to believe a proposition on the agent’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Why believe what people say?Leslie Stevenson - 1993 - Synthese 94 (3):429 - 451.
    The basic alternatives seem to be either a Humean reductionist view that any particular assertion needs backing with inductive evidence for its reliability before it can retionally be believed, or a Reidian criterial view that testimony is intrinscially, though defeasibly, credible, in the absence of evidence against its reliability.Some recent arguments from the constraints on interpreting any linguistic performances as assertions with propositional content have some force against the reductionist view. We thus have reason to accept the criterial view, at (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  23.  37
    Can We Forget What We Know in a False‐Belief Task? An Investigation of the True‐Belief Default.Paula Rubio-Fernández - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (1):218-241.
    It has been generally assumed in the Theory of Mind literature of the past 30 years that young children fail standard false-belief tasks because they attribute their own knowledge to the protagonist. Contrary to the traditional view, we have recently proposed that the children's bias is task induced. This alternative view was supported by studies showing that 3 year olds are able to pass a false-belief task that allows them to focus on the protagonist, without drawing their attention to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  58
    What the Old Right of Necessity Can Do for the Contemporary Global Poor.Alejandra Mancilla - 2017 - Journal of Applied Philosophy:607-620.
    Given the grim global statistics of extreme poverty and socioeconomic inequalities, moral and political philosophers have focused on the duties of justice and assistance that arise therefrom. What the needy are morally permitted to do for themselves in this context has been, however, a mostly overlooked question. Reviving a medieval and early modern account of the right of necessity, I propose that a chronically deprived agent has a right to take, use and/or occupy whatever material resources are required to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  5
    Doing What We Do Well: How Bioethicists Can Assist in Promoting Racial Justice.Mark Kuczewski - 2024 - American Journal of Bioethics 24 (10):15-17.
    Volume 24, Issue 10, October 2024, Page 15-17.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. What may we believe? What ought we to do?T. Spitzley, M. Holtje & W. Spohn (eds.) - 2013
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  8
    What can we believe?Vergilius Ture Anselm Ferm - 1948 - New York,: Philosophical Library.
  28. What do we see (when we do)?Sean D. Kelly - 2007 - In Thomas Baldwin (ed.), Reading Merleau-Ponty: On Phenomenology of Perception. New York: Routledge. pp. 107-128.
    1. The philosophical problem of what we see My topic revolves around what is apparently a very basic question. Stripped of all additions and in its leanest, most economical form, this is the question: "What do we see?" But in this most basic form the question admits of at least three different interpretations. In the first place, one might understand it to be an epistemological question, perhaps one with skeptical overtones. "What do we see?", on this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29.  6
    Doing what's right: how to fight for what you believe-- and make a difference.Tavis Smiley - 2000 - New York: Doubleday.
    Black Entertainment Television (BET) talk show host Tavis Smiley, in an impassioned call to arms, sets forth the tools we can use to stand up for what we believe in and help transform our communities, our lives, and our world. Tavis Smiley isn't alone in pointing out that our neighborhoods are unsafe, our communities are unraveling, and our most basic values--civility, a sense of justice, integrity, and responsibility--are under attack, from the Oval Office to the corner office. But (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Telling Others to Do What You Believe Is Morally Wrong: The Case of Confucius and Zai Wo.Frederick Choo - 2019 - Asian Philosophy 29 (2):106-115.
    Can it ever be morally justifiable to tell others to do what we ourselves believe is morally wrong to do? The common sense answer is no. It seems that we should never tell others to do something if we think it is morally wrong to do that act. My first goal is to argue that in Analects 17.21, Confucius tells his disciple not to observe a ritual even though Confucius himself believes that it is morally wrong that one (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31. Who knows what and who can we believe? Epistemological beliefs are beliefs about knowledge (mostly) to be attained from others.Rainer Bromme, Dorothe Kienhues & Torsten Porsch - 2010 - In Lisa D. Bendixen & Florian C. Feucht (eds.), Personal epistemology in the classroom: theory, research, and implications for practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  4
    What's the least I can believe and still be a Christian?: a guide to what matters most: new edition with study guide.Martin Thielen - 2013 - Louisville, Kentucky: Westminster John Knox Press.
    Pastor and author Martin Thielen has compiled a list of ten things people need to believe, and ten things they don't, in order to be a Christian. This lively and engaging book will be a help to seekers as well as a comfort to believers who may find themselves questioning some of the assumptions they grew up with. With an accessible, storytelling style that's grounded in solid biblical scholarship, Thielen shows how Christians don't need to believe that sinners (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  54
    Moral Blindness and Moral Responsibility: What can we learn from Rhoda Penmark?Laurie Calhoun - 1996 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 13 (1):41-50.
    ABSTRACT The cases devised by moral philosophers are often abstract and sterile to the point of precluding the most important function of emotion in our dealings with real people in real situations. Far from thinking that morality is exclusively a matter of rational assessment of the morally relevant features of a situation, I believe that rationality has little if anything to do with moral conduct, and I hope to illustrate this through a consideration of what precisely is amiss (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  75
    Heidegger on ontological education, or: How we become what we are.Iain Thomson - 2001 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 44 (3):243 – 268.
    Heidegger presciently diagnosed the current crisis in higher education. Contemporary theorists like Bill Readings extend and update Heidegger's critique, documenting the increasing instrumentalization, professionalization, vocationalization, corporatization, and technologization of the modern university, the dissolution of its unifying and guiding ideals, and, consequently, the growing hyper-specialization and ruinous fragmentation of its departments. Unlike Heidegger, however, these critics do not recognize such disturbing trends as interlocking symptoms of an underlying ontological problem and so they provide no positive vision for the future of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  35.  9
    What We Do Not Know in Common Experience.Bernard Williams - 1995 - Diogenes 43 (169):37-38.
    Whatever our profession we are all engulfed in daily life and in the obscurity and density of the mental world. Who is this “I” that finds expression in such a wide variety of societies, in the convictions of the group and temperament of the individual self, in all that I perceive imperfectly and that makes me me? What does this sometimes slippery, sometimes thorny “I” say about the various attitudes towards knowing: the things I desperately want to know, things (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  45
    What Do We Owe to Patients Who Leave Against Medical Advice? The Ethics of AMA Discharges.Leenoy Hendizadeh, Paula Goodman-Crews, Jeannette Martin & Eli Weber - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (2):139-145.
    Discharges against medical advice (AMA) make up a significant number of hospital discharges in the United States, and often involve vulnerable patients who struggle to obtain adequate medical care. Unfortunately, much of the AMA discharge process focuses on absolving the medical center of liability for what happens to these patients once they leave the acute setting. Comparatively little attention is paid to the ethical obligations of the medical team once an informed decision to leave the acute care setting AMA (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  34
    How we remember what we can do.Gunnar Declerck - 2015 - Socioaffective Neuroscience and Psychology 5.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38. What We Together Can (Be Required to) Do.Felix Pinkert - 2014 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 38 (1):187-202.
    In moral and political philosophy, collective obligations are promising “gap-stoppers” when we find that we need to assert some obligation, but can not plausibly ascribe this obligation to individual agents. Most notably, Bill Wringe and Jesse Tomalty discuss whether the obligations that correspond to socio-economic human rights are held by states or even by humankind at large. The present paper aims to provide a missing piece for these discussions, namely an account of the conditions under which obligations can apply to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  39.  8
    How can we Learn what Veritatis Splendor has to Teach?Alasdair MacIntyre - 1994 - The Thomist 58 (2):171-195.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:HOW CAN WE LEARN WHAT VER/TATIS SPLENDOR HAS TO TEACH? ALASDAIR MAclNTYRE University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana V-ERITATIS SPLENDOR can be read in two very different ways. It can be read, and of course it should be ad, as a papal encyclical, a piece of authoritative Christian teaching. As such, it is addressed to the Catholic bishops and its subject-matter is not only Christian moral teaching (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  40. Causal powers: what are they? why do we need them? what can be done with them and what cannot?Nancy Cartwright - unknown
    What are causal powers and why should we believe in them? Causal powers are now a central topic in metaphysics but my defence of them does not begin there, but rather in studies of the practices of the sciences, especially in my case, of physics and economics. Both of these use the analytic method: they ascertain the behaviour that would result from the operation of a cause ‘in isolation’; then take this behaviour to provide the ‘contribution’ that that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41.  19
    Temporal Truth and Bivalence: an Anachronistic Formal Approach to Aristotle’s De Interpretatione 9.Luiz Henrique Lopes dos Santos - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):59-79.
    Regarding the famous Sea Battle Argument, which Aristotle presents in De Interpretatione 9, there has never been a general agreement not only about its correctness but also, and mainly, about what the argument really is. According to the most natural reading of the chapter, the argument appeals to a temporal concept of truth and concludes that not every statement is always either true or false. However, many of Aristotle’s followers and commentators have not adopted this reading. I believe (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  46
    What can we be forced to do?Gerald Dworkin - 1991 - Journal of Social Philosophy 22 (2):40-48.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. What do we owe others as a matter of global justice and does national membership matter?Gillian Brock - 2008 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 11 (4):433-448.
    David Miller offers us a sophisticated account of how we can reconcile global obligations and duties to co?nationals. In this article I focus on four weaknesses with his account such as the following two. First, there remains considerable unclarity about the strength of the positive duties we have to non?nationals and how these measure up relative to other positive duties, such as the ones Miller believes we have to co?nationals to implement civil, political, or social rights. Second, just how responsibilities (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  44. What Do We Mean by “True” in Scientific Realism?Robert W. P. Luk - 2020 - Foundations of Science 25 (3):845-856.
    A crucial aspect of scientific realism is what do we mean by true. In Luk’s theory and model of scientific study, a theory can be believed to be “true” but a model is only accurate. Therefore, what do we mean by a “true” theory in scientific realism? Here, we focus on exploring the notion of truth by some thought experiments and we come up with the idea that truth is related to what we mean by the same. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  58
    We cannot empathize with what we do not recognize: Perceptions of structural versus interpersonal racism in South Africa.Melike M. Fourie & Samantha L. Moore-Berg - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Recent research suggests holding a structural, rather than interpersonal, understanding of racism is associated with greater impetus to address racial disparities. We believe greater acknowledgment of structural racism also functions to mitigate against empathic failures in response to structural injustices. Given South Africa’s situatedness as a country characterized by historical racialized oppression and continuing unjust legacies, it is appropriate to examine these ideas there. Across three studies, we tested the hypotheses that members of advantaged groups’ perspective taking and empathic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  57
    Comparative effectiveness research: what to do when experts disagree about risks.Reidar K. Lie, Francis K. L. Chan, Christine Grady, Vincent H. Ng & David Wendler - 2017 - BMC Medical Ethics 18 (1):42.
    Ethical issues related to comparative effectiveness research, or research that compares existing standards of care, have recently received considerable attention. In this paper we focus on how Ethics Review Committees should evaluate the risks of comparative effectiveness research. We discuss what has been a prominent focus in the debate about comparative effectiveness research, namely that it is justified when “nothing is known” about the comparative effectiveness of the available alternatives. We argue that this focus may be misleading. Rather, we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  9
    God of our fathers?: do we know what we believe?Peter Vardy - 1987 - London: Darton, Longman, and Todd.
  48.  9
    (1 other version)What Can (and Cannot) Be Said About the Distinction Between Religious Experience and Psychopathology.Mohammed Abouelleil Rashed - 2024 - Philosophy Psychiatry and Psychology 31 (3):219-222.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:What Can (and Cannot) Be Said About the Distinction Between Religious Experience and PsychopathologyMohammed Abouelleil Rashed, MD, PhDThe distinction between religious experience and psychopathology as a puzzle to be pondered, debated, clarified, and analyzed is an example of a thoroughly modern problem. It is modern in that the distinction can only make sense if our starting assumption is the existence of unique and separate types of experience that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  33
    Comparative effectiveness research: what to do when experts disagree about risks.K. Lie Reidar, K. L. Chan Francis, Grady Christine, Ng Vincent & Wendler David - 2017 - BMC Medical Ethics 18 (1):42.
    Background: Ethical issues related to comparative effectiveness research, or research that compares existing standards of care, have recently received considerable attention. In this paper we focus on how Ethics Review Committees should evaluate the risks of comparative effectiveness research. Main text: We discuss what has been a prominent focus in the debate about comparative effectiveness research, namely that it is justified when “nothing is known” about the comparative effectiveness of the available alternatives. We argue that this focus may be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  12
    What is the purpose of nurse education (and what should it be)?Freya Collier-Sewell & Sebastian Monteux - 2024 - Nursing Inquiry 31 (3):e12640.
    Can we take the purpose of nurse education for granted, and, more importantly, should we? That is the issue at stake in this paper. The question of purpose is conspicuously absent in the nursing literature; our aim here is to urge that it not be overlooked by demonstrating its importance to the future of nursing. We approach the question of nurse education's purpose in concrete and speculative terms through two distinct yet interrelated questions: what is the purpose of nurse (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 963